vendredi 25 janvier 2013

Histoires Racontées.

Céline, A Noeud Coulant, s.d.

Nous voici encore seuls. Tout cela est si lent, si lourd, si triste... Bientôt je serai vieux. Et ce sera fini. Il est venu tant de monde dans ma chambre. Ils ont dit des choses. Ils ne m'ont pas dit grand-chose. Ils sont partis. Ils sont devenus vieux, misérables et lents chacun dans un coin du monde.

Hier à huit heures Madame Bérenge, la concierge, est morte. Une grande tempête s'élève de la nuit. Tout en haut, où nous sommes, la maison tremble. C'était une douce et gentille et fidèle amie. Demain on l'enterre rue des Saules. Elle était vraiment vieille, tout au bout de la vieillesse. Je lui ai dit dès le premier jour quand elle a toussé : "Ne vous allongez pas surtout !... Restez assise dans votre lit !" Je me méfiais. Et puis voilà... Et puis tant pis.

Je n'ai pas toujours pratiqué la médecine, cette merde. Je vais leur écrire qu'elle est morte Madame Bérenge à ceux qui m'ont connu, qui l'ont connue. Où sont-ils ?

Je voudrais que la tempête fasse encore bien plus de boucan, que les toits s'écroulent, que le printemps ne revienne plus, que notre maison disparaisse.

Elle savait Madame Bérenge que tous les chagrins viennent dans les lettres. Je ne sais plus à qui écrire... Tous ces gens sont loin... Ils ont changé d'âme pour mieux trahir, mieux oublier, parler toujours d'autre chose...

Vieille Madame Bérenge, son chien qui louche on le prendra, on l'emmènera...

Tout le chagrin des lettres, depuis vingt ans bientôt, s'est arrêté chez elle. Il est là dans l'odeur de la mort récente, l'incroyable aigre goût... Il vient d'éclore... Il est là... Il rôde... Il nous connaît, nous le connaissons à présent. Il ne s'en ira plus jamais. Il faut éteindre le feu dans la loge. A qui vais-je écrire ? Je n'ai plus personne. Plus un être pour recueillir doucement l'esprit gentil des morts... pour parler après ça plus doucement des choses... Courage pour soi tout seul !

Sur la fin ma vieille bignolle, elle ne pouvait plus rien dire. Elle étouffait, elle me retenait par la main... Le facteur est entré. Il l'a vue mourir. Un petit hoquet. C'est tout. Bien des gens sont venus chez elle autrefois pour me demander. Ils sont repartis loin, très loin dans l'oubli, se chercher une âme. Le facteur a ôté son képi. Je pourrais moi dire toute ma haine. Je sais. Je le ferai plus tard s'ils ne reviennent pas. J'aime mieux raconter des histoires. J'en raconterai de telles qu'ils reviendront, exprès, pour me tuer, des quatre coins du monde. Alors ce sera fini et je serai content.

Louis-Ferdinand Destouches dit Céline, Mort à Crédit, Éditions Gallimard, coll. Folio, 1952, p.11-12.    

vendredi 18 janvier 2013

Anti Market E02.

Tomas Saraceno, Galaxies Forming along Filaments, Like Droplets along the Strands of a Spider's Web, 2009.

What would one expect to emerge from such populations of more or less centralized organizations and more or less decentralized markets ? The answer is, a world-economy, or a large zone of economic coherence. The term, which should not be confused with that of a global economy, was coined by Immanuel Wallerstein, and later adapted by Braudel so as not to depend on a conception of history in terms of a unilineal progression of modes of production. From Wallerstein Braudel takes the spatial definition of a world-economy : an economically autonomous portion of the planet, perhaps coexisting with other such regions, with a definite geographical structure : a core of cities which dominate it, surrounded by yet other economically active cities subordinated to the core and forming a middle zone, and finally a periphery of completely exploited supply zones. The role of core of the European world-economy has been historically played by several cities : first Venice in the fourteenth century, followed by Antwerp and Genoa in the fifteenth and sixteenth. Amsterdam then dominated it for the next two centuries, followed by London and then New York. Today, we may be witnessing the end of American supremacy and the role of core seems to be moving to Tokyo. (16)

Interestingly, those cities which play the role of core, seem to generate in their populations of firms, very few large ones. For instance, when Venice played this role, no large organizations emerged in it, even though they already existed in nearby Florence. Does this contradict the thesis that capitalism has always been monopolistic ? I think not. What happens is that, in this case, Venice as a whole played the role of a monopoly : it completely controlled access to the spice and luxury markets in the Levant. Within Venice, everything seemed like "free competition", and yet its rich merchants enjoyed tremendous advantages over any foreign rival, whatever its size. Perhaps this can help explain the impression classical economists had of a competitive stage of capitalism : when the Dutch or the British advocated "free competition" internally is precisely when their cities as a whole held a virtual monopoly on world trade. 

World-economies, then, present a pattern of concentric circles around a center, defined by relations of subordination. Besides this spatial structure, Wallerstein and Braudel add a temporal one : a world-economy expands and contracts in a variety of rhythms of different lengths : from short term business cycles to longer term Kondratiev cycles which last approximately fifty years. While the domination by core cities gives a world-economy its spatial unity, these cycles give it a temporal coherence : prices and wages move in unison over the entire area. Prices are, of course, much higher at the center than at the periphery, and this makes everything flow towards the core : Venice, Amsterdam, London and New York, as they took their turn as dominant centers, became "universal warehouses" where one could find any product from anywhere in the world. And yet, while respecting these differences, all prices moved up and down following these nonlinear rhythms, affecting even those firms belonging to the antimarket, which needed to consider those fluctuations when setting their own prices. 

These self-organized patterns in time and space which define world-economies were first discovered in analytical studies of historical data. The next step is to use synthetic techniques and create the conditions under which they can emerge in our models. In fact, bottom-up computer simulations of urban economics where spatial and temporal patterns spontaneously emerge already exist. For example, Peter Allen has created simulations of nonlinear urban dynamics as meshworks of interdependent economic functions. Unlike earlier mathematical models of the distribution of urban centers, which assumed perfect rationality on the part of economic agents, and where spatial patterns resulted from the optimal use of some resource such as transportation, here patterns emerge from a dynamic of conflict and cooperation. As the flows of goods, services and people in and out of these cities change, some urban centers grow while others decay. Stable patterns of coexisting centers arise as bifurcations occur in the growing city networks taking them from attractor to attractor. (17)

Something like Allen's approach would be useful to model one of the two things that stitch world-economies together, according to Braudel : trade circuits. However, to generate the actual spatial patterns that we observe in the history of Europe, we need to include the creation of chains of subordination among these cities, of hierarchies of dependencies besides the meshworks of interdependencies. This would need the inclusion of monopolies and oligopolies, growing out of each cities meshworks of small producers and traders. We would also need to model the extensive networks of merchants and bankers with which dominant cities invaded their surrounding urban centers, converting them into a middle zone at the service of the core. A dynamical system of trade circuits, animated by import-substitution dynamics within each city, and networks of merchants extending the reach of large firms of each city, may be able to give us some insight into the real historical dynamics of the European economy. (18)

Bottom-up economic models which generate temporal patterns have also been created. One of the most complex simulations in this area is the Systems Dynamics National Model at MIT. Unlike econometric simulations, where one begins at the macroeconomic level, this one is built up from the operating structure within corporations. Production processes within each industrial sector are modeled in detail. The decision-making behind price setting, for instance, is modeled using the know-how from real managers. The model includes many nonlinearities normally dismissed in classical economic models, like delays, bottlenecks and the inevitable friction due to bounded rationality. The simulation was not created with the purpose of confirming the existence of the Kondratiev wave, the fifty-two year cycle that can be observed in the history of wholesale prices for at least two centuries. In fact, the designers of the model were unaware of the literature on the subject. Yet, when the simulation began to unfold, it reached a bifurcation and a periodic attractor emerged in the system, which began pulsing to a fifty year beat. The crucial element in this dynamics seems to be the capital goods sector, the part of the industry that creates the machines that the rest of the economy uses. Whenever an intense rise in global demand occurs, firms need to expand and so need to order new machines. But when the capital goods sector in turn expands to meet this demand it needs to order from itself. This creates a positive feedback loop that pushes the system towards a bifurcation. (19)

Insights coming from running simulations like these can, in turn, be used to build other simulations and to suggest directions for historical research to follow. We can imagine parallel computers in the near future running simulations combining all the insights from the ones we just discussed : spatial networks of cities, breathing at different rhythms, and housing evolving populations of organizations and meshworks of interdependent skills. If power relations are included, monopolies and oligopolies will emerge and we will be able to explore the genesis and evolution of the antimarket. If we include the interactions between different forms of organizations, then the relationships between economic and military institutions may be studied. As Galbraith has pointed out, in today's economy nothing goes against the market, nothing is a better representative of the planning system, as he calls it, than the military-industrial complex. But we would be wrong in thinking that this is a modern phenomenon, something caused by "late capitalism". (20)

In the first core of the European world-economy, thirteenth century Venice, the alliance between monopoly power and military might was already in evidence. The Venetian arsenal, where all the merchant ships were built, was the largest industrial complex of its time. We can think of these ships as the fixed capital, the productive machinery of Venice, since they were used to do all the trade that kept her powerful; but at the same time, they were military machines used to enforce her monopolistic practices. (21)

When the turn of Amsterdam and London came to be the core, the famous Companies of Indias with which they conquered the Asian world-economy, transforming it into a periphery of Europe, were also hybrid military-economic institutions. We have already mentioned the role that French armories and arsenals in the eighteenth century, and American ones in the nineteenth, played in the birth of mass production techniques. Frederick Taylor, the creator of the modern system for the control the labor process, learned his craft in military arsenals. That nineteenth century radical economists did not understand this hybrid nature of the antimarket can be seen from the fact that Lenin himself welcomed Taylorism into revolutionary Russia as a progressive force, instead of seeing for what it was : the imposition of a rigid command-hierarchy on the workplace. (22)

Unlike these thinkers, we should include in our simulations all the institutional interactions that historians have uncovered, to correctly model the hybrid economic-military structure of the antimarket. Perhaps by using these synthetic models as tools of exploration, as intuition synthesizers, so to speak, we will also be able to study the feasibility of counteracting the growth of the antimarket by a proliferation of meshworks of small producers. Multinational corporations, according to the influential theory of "transaction-costs", grow by swallowing up meshworks, by internalizing markets either through vertical or horizontal integration. (23)

They can do this thanks to their enormous economic power (most of them are oligopolies), and to their having access to intense economies of scale. However, meshworks of small producers interconnected via computer networks could have access to different, yet as intense economies of scale. A well studied example is the symbiotic collection of small textile firms that has emerged in an Italian region between Bologna and Venice. The operation of a few centralized textile corporations was broken down into a decentralized network of firms, in which entrepreneurs replace managers and short runs of specialized products replace large run of mass produced ones. Computer networks allow these small firms to react flexibly to sudden shifts in demand, so that no firm becomes overloaded while others sit idly with spare capacity. (24)

But more importantly, a growing pool of skills is thereby created, and because this pool has not been internalized by a large corporation, it can not be taken away. Hence this region will not suffer the fate of so many American company towns, which die after the corporation that feeds them moves elsewhere. This self-organized reservoirs of skills also explain why economic development cannot be exported to the third world via large transfers of capital invested in dams or other large structures. Economic development must emerge from within as meshworks of skills grow and proliferate. (25)

Computer networks are an important element here, since the savings in coordination costs that multinational corporations achieve by internalizing markets, can be enjoyed by small firms through the use of decentralizing technology. Computers may also help us to create a new approach to control within these small firms. The management approach used by large corporations was in fact developed during World War II under the name of Operations Research. Much as mass production techniques effected a transfer of a command hierarchy from military arsenals to civilian factories, management practices based on linear analysis carry with them the centralizing tendencies of the military institutions where they were born. Fresh approaches to these questions are now under development by nonlinear scientists, in which the role of managers is not to impose preconceived plans on workers, but to catalyze the emergence of meshworks of decision-making processes among them. (26)

Computers, in the form of embedded intelligence in the buildings that house small firms, can aid this catalytic process, allowing the firm's members to reach some measure of self-organization. Although these efforts are in their infancy, they may one day play a crucial role in adding some heterogeneity to a world-economy that's becoming increasingly homogenized.

Manuel De Landa, Markets and Antimarkets in the World Economy, 1996 (via Alamut). 

Notes.

16. Fernand Braudel, op. cit., Vol 3., p.25-38.
17. Peter M. Allen, Self-Organization in the Urban System in William C. Schieve and P.M.Allen (eds.), Self-Organization and Dissipative Structures : Applications in the Physical and the Social Sciences, University of Texas, Austin, 1982, p.136.
18. Fernand Braudel, op. cit., Vol 3., p.140-167 
19. J.D. Sterman, Nonlinear Dynamics in the World Economy : the Economic Long Wave in Peter Christiansen and R.D. Parmentier (eds.), Structure, Coherence and Chaos in Dynamical Systems, Manchester Univ. Press, Manchester, 1989.
20. John Galbraith, op. cit., p. 321.
21. Fernand Braudel, op. cit., Vol 2., p. 444.
22. Vladimir Lenin, The Immediate Tests of the Soviet Goverment. Collected Works, Vol 27, Moskow 1965. 
23. Jean-Francois Hennart, The Transaction Cost Theory of the Multinational Enterprise in Christos Pitelis and Roger Sudgen (eds.), The Nature of the Transnational Firm, Rutledge, London, 1991. 
24. Thomas W. Malone and John F. Rockart, Computers, Networks and the Corporation in Scientific American, Vol 265, Number 3, p.131. Also : 
Jane Jacobs, op. cit., p.40, 
Fernand Braudel, op cit, Vol 3, p. 630.
25. Jane Jacobs. op. cit., p.148.
26. F. Malik and G. Probst, Evolutionary Management in H. Ulrich and G. Probst (eds.) Self-Organization and Management of Social Systems, Springer Verlag, Berlin, 1984, p. 113. 

vendredi 11 janvier 2013

Anti Market E01.

Andreas Gursky, Chicago, Board of Trade II, 1999.

We tend to uncritically assume systematicity, as when one talks of the "capitalist system", instead of showing exactly how such systematic properties of the whole emerge from concrete historical processes. Worse yet, we then tend to reify such unaccounted-for systematicity, ascribing all kinds of causal powers to capitalism, to the extent that a clever writer can make it seem as if anything at all (from nonlinear dynamics itself to postmodernism or cyberculture) is the product of late capitalism. This basic mistake, which is, I believe, a major obstacle to a correct understanding of the nature of economic power, is partly the result of the purely top-down, analytical style that has dominated economic modeling from the eighteenth century. Both macroeconomics, which begins at the top with concepts like gross national product, as well as microeconomics, in which a system of preferences guides individual choice, are purely analytical in approach. Neither the properties of a national economy nor the ranked preferences of consumers are shown to emerge from historical dynamics. Marxism, is true, added to these models intermediate scale phenomena, like class struggle, and with it conflictive dynamics. But the specific way in which it introduced conflict, via the labor theory of value, has now been shown by Shraffa to be redundant, added from the top, so to speak, and not emerging from the bottom, from real struggles over wages, or the length of the working day, or for control over the production process. (4)

Besides a switch to a synthetic approach, as it is happening, for instance, in the evolutionary economics of Nelson and Winter in which the emphasis is on populations of organizations interacting nonlinearly, what we need here is a return to the actual details of economic history. Much has been learned in recent decades about these details, thanks to the work of materialist historians like Fernand Braudel, and it is to this historical data that we must turn to know what we need to model synthetically. Nowhere is this need for real history more evident that in the subject of the dynamics of economic power, defined as the capability to manipulate the prices of inputs and outputs of the production process as well as their supply and demand. In a peasant market, or even in a small town local market, everybody involved is a price taker : one shows up with merchandise, and sells it at the going prices which reflect demand and supply. But monopolies and oligopolies are price setters : the prices of their products need not reflect demand/supply dynamics, but rather their own power to control a given market share. (5)

When approaching the subject of economic power, one can safely ignore the entire field of linear mathematical economics (so-called competitive equilibrium economics), since there monopolies and oligopolies are basically ignored. Yet, even those thinkers who make economic power the center of their models, introduce it in a way that ignores historical facts. Authors writing in the Marxist tradition, place real history in a straight-jacket by subordinating it to a model of a progressive succession of modes of production. Capitalism itself is seen as maturing through a series of stages, the latest one of which is the monopolistic stage in this century. Even non-Marxists economists like Galbraith, agree that capitalism began as a competitive pursuit and stayed that way till the end of the nineteenth century, and only then it reached the monopolistic stage, at which point a planning system replaced market dynamics. 

However, Fernand Braudel has recently shown, with a wealth of historical data, that this picture is inherently wrong. Capitalism was, from its beginnings in the Italy of the thirteenth century, always monopolistic and oligopolistic. That is to say, the power of capitalism has always been associated with large enterprises, large that is, relative to the size of the markets where they operate. (6)

Also, it has always been associated with the ability to plan economic strategies and to control market dynamics, and therefore, with a certain degree of centralization and hierarchy. Within the limits of this presentation, I will not be able to review the historical evidence that supports this extremely important hypothesis, but allow me at least to extract some of the consequences that would follow if it turns out to be true. 

First of all, if capitalism has always relied on non-competitive practices, if the prices for its commodities have never been objectively set by demand/supply dynamics, but imposed from above by powerful economic decision-makers, then capitalism and the market have always been different entities. To use a term introduced by Braudel, capitalism has always been an "antimarket". This, of course, would seem to go against the very meaning of the word "capitalism", regardless of whether the word is used by Karl Marx or Ronald Reagan. For both nineteenth century radicals and twentieth century conservatives, capitalism is identified with an economy driven by market forces, whether one finds this desirable or not. Today, for example, one speaks of the former Soviet Union's "transition to a market economy", even though what was really supposed to happen was a transition to an antimarket : to large scale enterprises, with several layers of managerial strata, in which prices are set not taken. This conceptual confusion is so entrenched that I believe the only solution is to abandon the term "capitalism" completely, and to begin speaking of markets and antimarkets and their dynamics. 

This would have the added advantage that it would allow us to get rid of historical theories framed in terms of stages of progress, and to recognize the fact that antimarkets could have arisen anywhere, not just Europe, the moment the flows of goods through markets reach a certain critical level of intensity, so that organizations bent on manipulating these flows can emerge. Hence, the birth of antimarkets in Europe has absolutely nothing to do with a peculiarly European trait, such as rationality or a religious ethic of thrift. As is well known today, Europe borrowed most of its economic and accounting techniques, those techniques that are supposed to distinguish her as uniquely rational, from Islam. (7)

Many of the technological inventions that allowed her economy to take-off came from China. What needs explaining is not that antimarkets were born in Europe, but that they did not emerge in the economies of China or Islam, even though the volume of trade there was intense enough. Several historians explain this situation by invoking the repressive power of their respective states, which made large scale accumulation of capital impossible. (8)

Finally, and before we take a look at what a synthetic, bottom-up approach to the study of economic dynamics would be like, let me meet a possible objection to these remarks : the idea that "real" capitalism did not emerge till the nineteenth century industrial revolution, and hence that it could not have arisen anywhere else where these specific conditions did not exist. To criticize this position, Fernand Braudel has also shown that the idea that capitalism goes through stages, first commercial, then industrial and finally financial, is not supported by the available historical evidence. Venice in the fourteenth century and Amsterdam in the seventeenth, to cite only two examples, already show the coexistance of the three modes of capital in interaction. Moreover, other historians have recently shown that that specific form of industrial production which we tend to identify as "truly capitalist", that is, assembly-line mass production, was not born in economic organizations, but in military ones, beginning in France in the eighteenth century, and then in the United States in the nineteenth. It was military arsenals and armories that gave birth to these particularly oppressive control techniques of the production process, at least a hundred years before Henry Ford and his Model-T cars. (9)

This largely ignored military component of large scale enterprises is, I believe, another good reason to replace the term "capitalism" with a neologism like "the antimarket", since we can simply build this military component right into our definition of the term. 

Besides conceptual clarification of its terms, economics needs novel approaches to modeling in order to complement analysis of its concepts with synthesis of the emergent properties of the phenomena it concerns itself with. What would the models created by a bottom-up approach to the evolution of economics look like ? A convenient starting point for a description of such a complex simulation, is provided by the work of Nelson and Winter on evolutionary economics. In their work they begin at the bottom, at the level of the individual firm. Why not even lower, at the level of human individuals ? Because one important insight of their research is that large organizations, having developed routine procedures to handle many decisions, strongly constrain the choices of individual decision-makers, at least in most of the daily operation of the firm. These routines function as an "organizational memory" that maintains the identity of the firm from day to day. When a firm opens up a branch, for example, it moves some of it staff to that branch and a more or less accurate copy of this memory is transferred with them. (10)

Hence, the large firms that make up the antimarket, can be seen as replicators, much as animals and plants are. And in populations of such replicators we should be able to observe the emergence of the different commercial forms, from the family firm, to the limited liability partnership to the joint stock company. These three forms, which had already emerged by the fifteenth century, must be seen as arising, like those of animals and plants, from slow accumulations of traits which later become consolidated into more or less permanent structures, and not, of course, as the manifestation of some pre-existing essence. In short, both animal and plant species as well as "institutional species" are historical constructions, the emergence of which bottom-up models can help us study. 

It is important to emphasize that we are not dealing with biological metaphors here. Any kind of replicating system which produces variable copies of itself, coupled with any kind of sorting device, is capable of evolving new forms. This basic insight is now exploited technologically in the so-called "genetic algorithm", which allows programmers to breed computer software instead of painstakingly coding it by hand. A population of computer programs is allowed to reproduce with some variation, and the programmer plays the role of sorting device, steering the population towards the desired form. The same idea is what makes Artificial Life projects work. Hence, when we say that the forms the antimarket has taken are evolved historical constructions we do not mean to say that they are metaphorically like organic forms, but that they are produced by a process which embodies the same engineering diagram as the one which generates organic forms. Another example may help clarify this. When one says, as leftists used to say, that "class-struggle is the motor of history", one is using the word "motor" in a metaphorical way. On the other hand, to say that a hurricane is a steam motor is not to use the term metaphorically, but literally : one is saying that the hurricane embodies the same engineering diagram as a steam motor : it uses a reservoir of heat and operates via differences of temperature circulated through a Carnot cycle. The same is true of the genetic algorithm. Anything that replicates, such as patterns of behavior transmitted by imitation, or rules and norms transmitted by enforced repetition can give rise to novel forms, when populations of them are subjected to selection pressures. And the traits that are thus accumulated can become consolidated into a permanent structure by codification, as when informal routines become written rules. (11)

In this case, we have the diagram of a process which generates hierarchical structures, whether large institutions rigidly controlled by their rules or organic structures rigidly controlled by their genes. There are, however, other structure-generating processes which result in decentralized assemblages of heterogeneous components. Unlike a species, an ecosystem is not controlled by a genetic program : it integrates a variety of animals and plants in a food web, interlocking them together into what has been called a "meshwork structure". The dynamics of such meshworks are currently under intense investigation and something like their abstract diagram is beginning to emerge. (12)

From this research, it is becoming increasingly clear that small markets, that is, local markets without too many middlemen, embody this diagram : they allow the assemblage of human beings by interlocking complementary demands. These markets are indeed, self-organized decentralized structures : they arise spontaneously without the need for central planning. As dynamic entities they have absolutely nothing to do with an "invisible hand", since models based on Adam Smith's concept operate in a frictionless environment in which agents have perfect rationality and all information flows freely. Yet, by eliminating nonlinearities, these models preclude the spontaneous emergence of order, which depends crucially on friction : delays, bottlenecks, imperfect decision-making and so on. 

The concept of a meshwork can be applied not only to the area of exchange, but also to that of industrial production. Jane Jacobs has created a theory of the dynamics of networks of small producers meshed together by their interdependent functions, and has collected some historical evidence to support her claims. The basic idea is that certain relatively backward cities in the past, Venice when it was still subordinated to Byzantium, or the network New York-Boston-Philadelphia when still a supply zone for the British empire, engage in what she calls, import-substitution dynamics. Because of their subordinated position, they must import most manufactured products, and export raw materials. Yet, meshworks of small producers within the city, by interlocking their skills can begin to replace those imports with local production, which can then be exchanged with other backward cities. In the process, new skills and new knowledge is generated, new products begin to be imported, which in turn, become the raw materials for a new round of import-substitution. Nonlinear computer simulations have been created of this process, and they confirm Jacobs' intuition : a growing meshwork of skills is a necessary condition for urban morphodynamics. The meshwork as a whole is decentralized, and it does not grow by planning, but by a kind of creative drift. (13)

Of course, this dichotomy between command hierarchies and meshworks should not be taken too rigidly : in reality, once a market grows beyond a certain size, it spontaneously generates a hierarchy of exchange, with prestige goods at the top and elementary goods, like food, at the bottom. Command structures, in turn, generate meshworks, as when hierarchical organizations created the automobile and then a meshwork of services (repair shops, gas stations, motels and so on), grew around it. (14)

More importantly, one should not romantically identify meshworks with that which is "desirable" or "revolutionary", since there are situations when they increase the power of hierarchies. For instance, oligopolistic competition between large firms is sometimes kept away from price wars by the system of interlocking directorates, in which representatives of large banks or insurance companies sit in the boards of directors of these oligopolies. In this case, a meshwork of hierarchies is almost equivalent to a monopoly. (15)

And yet, however complex the interaction between hierarchies and meshworks, the distinction is real : the former create structures out of elements sorted out into homogenous ranks, the latter articulates heterogeneous elements as such, without homogenization. A bottom-up approach to economic modeling should represent institutions as varying mixtures of command and market components, perhaps in the form of combinations of negative feedback loops, which are homogenizing, and positive feedback, which generates heterogeneity. 

Manuel De Landa, Markets and Antimarkets in the World Economy, 1996 (via Alamut).

Notes.

4. Geoff Hodgson, Critique of Wright 1 : Labour and Profits in Ian Steedman (ed.) The Value Controversy, Verso, London, 1981, p.93.
5. John Keneth Galbraith, The New Industrial State, Houghton Mifflin, Boston, 1978, p.24.
6. Fernand Braudel, Civilization and Capitalism, 15th-18th Century. Vol 2., Harper and Row, New York, 1982, p.229.
7. Ibid, p.559-561.
8. William H. McNeill, The Pursuit of Power, University of Chicago Press, 1982, p.49.
9. Merritt Roe Smith, Army Ordnance and the "American system" of Manufacturing, 1815-1861 in Merritt Roe Smith (ed.), Military Enterprise and Technological Change, MIT Press, 1987, p.47.
10. Richard Nelson and Sidney Winter, An Evolutionary Theory of Economic Change, Belknap Press, Cambridge Mass, 1982, p.98.
11. Richard Dawkins, The Selfish Gene, Oxford University Press, New York, 1989, ch.11.
12. Stuart Kauffman, The Evolution of Economic Webs in Philip Anderson, Kenneth Arrow and David Pines (eds.), The Economy as an Evolving Complex System, Addison-Wesley, 1988.
13. Jane Jacobs, Cities and the Wealth of Nations, Random House, New York, 1984, p.133.
14. The dichotomy Meshwork/Hierarchy is a special case of what Deleuze and Guattari call Smooth/Striated or Rhizome/Tree. Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari, 1440 : The Smooth and the Striated in A Thousand Plateaus, University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, 1987, ch.14.
15. John R. Munkirs and James I. Sturgeon, Oligopolistic Cooperation : Conceptual and Empirical Evidence of Market Structure Evolution in Marc. R. Tool and Warren J. Samuels (eds.), The Economy as a System of Power, Transaction Press, New Brunswick, 1989, p.343.

vendredi 4 janvier 2013

A Bicyclette.

Photographie non attribuée, Vietcong à bicyclctte, s.d.

Le roulement à billes a été inventé il y a un siècle. Grâce à lui le coefficient de frottement est devenu mille fois plus faible. En ajustant convenablement un roulement à billes entre deux meules néolithiques, un Indien peut moudre à présent autant de grain en une journée que ses ancêtres en une semaine. Le roulement à billes a aussi rendu possible l'invention de la bicyclette, c'est-à-dire l'utilisation de la roue, - la dernière, sans doute, des grandes inventions néolithiques -, au service de la mobilité obtenue par la force musculaire humaine. Le roulement à billes est ici le symbole d'une rupture définitive avec la tradition et des directions opposées que peut prendre le développement. L'homme peut se déplacer sans l'aide d'aucun outil. Pour transporter chaque gramme de son corps sur un kilomètre en dix minutes, il dépense 0,75 calorie. Il forme une machine thermodynamique plus rentable que n'importe quel véhicule à moteur et plus efficace que la plupart des animaux. Proportionnellement à son poids, quand il se déplace, il produit plus de travail que le rat ou le bœuf, et moins que le cheval ou l'esturgeon. Avec ce rendement, il a peuplé la terre et fait son histoire. A ce même niveau, les sociétés agraires consacrent moins de 5 % et les nomades moins de 8 % de leur budget-temps à circuler hors des habitations ou des campements.  

A bicyclette, l'homme va de trois à quatre fois plus vite qu'à pied, tout en dépensant cinq fois moins d'énergie. En terrain plat, il lui suffit alors de dépenser 0,15 calorie pour transporter un gramme de son corps sur un kilomètre. La bicyclette est un outil parfait qui permet à l'homme d'utiliser au mieux son énergie métabolique pour se mouvoir : ainsi outillé, l'homme dépasse le rendement de toutes les machines et celui de tous les animaux.  

Si l'on ajoute à l'invention du roulement à billes celles de la roue à rayons et du pneu, cette conjonction a pour 1'histoire du transport plus d'importance que tous les autres événements, à l'exception de trois d'entre eux. D'abord, à 1'aube de la civilisation, l'invention de la roue transféra les fardeaux des épaules des hommes à la brouette. Puis au Moyen Age, en Europe, les inventions du bridon, du collier d'épaules et du fer à cheval multiplièrent par cinq le rendement thermodynamique du cheval et transformèrent l'économie en permettant de fréquents labourages et la rotation des assolements. De plus, elles mirent à la portée des paysans des champs éloignés : ainsi on vit la population rurale passer de hameaux de six familles à des villages de cent feux, groupés autour de l'église, du marché, de la prison et, plus tard, de l'école. Cela rendit possible la mise en culture de terres situées plus au nord et déplaça le centre du pouvoir vers des régions plus froides. Enfin, la construction par les Portugais au XVe siècle des premiers vaisseaux de haute mer posa, sous 1'égide du capitalisme européen naissant, les fondements d'une économie de marché mondiale et de l'impérialisme moderne.  
  
L'invention du roulement à billes marqua une quatrième révolution. Elle permit de choisir entre plus de liberté et d'équité d'une part et une vitesse et une exploitation accrues d'autre part. Le roulement à billes est un élément fondamental dans deux formes de déplacement, respectivement symbolisées par le vélo et par l'automobile. Le vélo élève la mobilité autogène de l'homme jusqu'à un nouveau degré, au-delà duquel il n'y a plus en théorie de progrès possible. A l'opposé, la cabine individuelle accélérée a rendu les sociétés capables de s'engager dans un rituel de la vitesse qui progressivement les paralyse.  

Que s'établisse un monopole d'emploi rituel d'un outil potentiellement utile n'est pas un phénomène nouveau. Il y a des millénaires, la roue déchargea le porteur esclave de son fardeau, mais seulement dans les pays d'Eurasie. Au Mexique, bien que très connue, la roue ne fut jamais utilisée pour le transport, mais exclusivement pour fabriquer de petites voitures destinées à des dieux en miniature. Que la charrette ait été un objet tabou dans l'Amérique d'avant Cortès ne doit pas nous étonner davantage que le fait que le vélo soit tabou dans la circulation moderne.  

Il n'est absolument pas nécessaire que l'invention du roulement à billes serve, à l'avenir, à augmenter encore la consommation d'énergie et engendre ainsi le manque de temps, le gaspillage de l'espace et des privilèges de classe. Si le nouveau degré de mobilité autogène offert par le vélo était protégé de la dévaluation, de la paralysie et des risques corporels pour le cycliste, alors il serait possible de garantir à tout le monde une mobilité optimale et d'en finir avec un système qui privilégie les uns et exploite les autres au maximum. On pourrait contrôler les formes d'urbanisation, si la structuration de l'espace était liée à l'aptitude des hommes à s'y déplacer. Limiter absolument la vitesse, c'est retenir la forme la plus décisive d'aménagement et d'organisation de l'espace. Selon qu'on l'utilise dans une technique vaine ou profitable, le roulement à billes change de valeur. Un vélo n'est pas seulement un outil thermodynamique efficace, il ne coûte pas cher. Malgré son très bas salaire, un Chinois consacre moins d'heures de travail à l'achat d'une bicyclette qui durera longtemps qu'un Américain à l'achat d'une voiture bientôt hors d'usage. Les aménagements publics nécessaires pour les bicyclettes sont comparativement moins chers que la réalisation d'une infrastructure adaptée à des véhicules rapides. Pour les vélos, il ne faut de routes goudronnées que dans les zones de circulation dense, et les gens qui vivent loin d'une telle route ne sont pas isolés, comme ils le seraient s'ils dépendaient de trains ou de voitures. La bicyclette élargit le rayon d'action personnel sans interdire de passer où l'on ne peut rouler: il suffit alors de pousser son vélo.  

Le vélo nécessite une moindre place. Là où se gare une seule voiture, on peut ranger dix-huit vélos, et l'espace qu'il faut pour faire passer une voiture livre a passage à trente vélos. Pour faire franchir un pont à 40 000 personnes en une heure, il faut deux voies d'une certaine largeur si l'on utilise des trains, quatre si l'on utilise des autobus, douze pour des voitures, et une seule si tous traversent à bicyclette. Le vélo est le seul véhicule qui conduise l'homme de porte à porte, à n'importe quelle heure, et par l'itinéraire de son choix. Le cycliste peut atteindre de nouveaux endroits sans que son vélo désorganise un espace qui pourrait mieux servir à la vie.  

La bicyclette permet de se déplacer plus vite, sans pour autant consommer des quantités élevées d'un espace, d'un temps ou d'une énergie devenus également rares. Chaque kilomètre de trajet est parcouru plus rapidement, et la distance totale franchie annuellement est aussi plus élevée. Avec un vélo, l'homme peut partager les bienfaits d'une conquête technique, sans prétendre régenter les horaires, l'espace, ou l'énergie d'autrui. Un cycliste est maître de sa propre mobilité sans empiéter sur celle des autres. Ce nouvel outil ne crée que des besoins qu'il peut satisfaire, au lieu que chaque accroissement de l'accélération produit par des véhicules à moteur crée de nouvelles exigences de temps et d'espace.  

Le roulement à billes et les pneus permettent à l'homme d'instaurer un nouveau rapport entre son temps de vie et son espace de vie, entre son propre territoire et le rythme de son être, sans usurper l'espace-temps et le rythme biologique d'autrui. Ces avantages d'un mode de déplacement moderne, fondé sur la force individuelle, sont évidents, pourtant en général on les ignore. On ne se sert du roulement à billes que pour produire des machines plus puissantes; on avance toujours l'idée qu'un moyen de transport est d'autant meilleur qu'il roule plus vite, mais on se dispense de la prouver. La raison en est que si l'on cherchait à démontrer la chose, on découvrirait qu'il n'en est rien aujourd'hui. La proposition contraire est, en vérité, facile à établir: à présent, on accepte son contenu avec réticence, demain elle deviendra évidente.  

Un combat acharné entre vélos et moteurs vient à peine de s'achever. Au Vietnam, une armée sur-industrialisée n'a pu défaire un petit peuple qui se déplaçait à la vitesse de ses bicyclettes. La leçon est claire. Des armées dotées d'un gros potentiel d'énergie peuvent supprimer des hommes - à la fois ceux qu'elles défendent et ceux qu'elles combattent -, mais elles ne peuvent pas grand-chose contre un peuple qui se défend lui-même. Il reste à savoir si les Vietnamiens utiliseront dans une économie de paix ce que leur a appris la guerre et s'ils sont prêts à garder les valeurs mêmes qui leur ont permis de vaincre. Il est à craindre qu'au nom du développement industriel et de la consommation croissante d'énergie, les Vietnamiens ne s'infligent à eux-mêmes une défaite en brisant de leurs mains ce système équitable, rationnel et autonome, imposé par les bombardiers américains à mesure qu'ils les privaient d'essence, de moteurs et de routes.

Ivan Illich, Chapitre VIII - Les Degrés de Mobilité in Énergie et Équité, Éditions du Seuil, 1973.